Skip main navigation

Descartes, Boyle, and Le Grand on forms

In this article, we will look in some detail at the critique of forms in Descartes, Boyle, and Le Grand.
© University of Groningen

In the last step, you have read three exerpts from authors criticising the notion of form. Here, we will see in some detail on what grounds these authors criticised the notion of form. Also, we will see that according to one of them, Boyle, the word form could be retained, provided it be interpreted in a very specific way.

Descartes on forms

Consider again the following passage from Descartes’s letter to Regius:

Substantial forms were introduced by the philosophers only in order to account for the proper actions of natural things, of which forms were supposed to be the principles and roots. … But the natural actions of things cannot be explained by such substantial forms, as even their defenders admit that they do not understand what they are. So if they say that some action proceeds from a substantial form, it is as if they said that it proceeds from something they do not understand, and that explains nothing. Therefore, these forms must not be introduced in any way to account for the causes of the natural actions of things.
In this letter, Descartes notes that for the scholastic philosophers, the form of a body was the inner source of its physical properties. And that seems correct. As we have seen, for scholastic thinkers such as Thomas Aquinas and Francisco Suárez, the form of a body was the inner source of its actions and motions.
Descartes’s complaint here is that these thinkers never went on to explain just what kind of thing the form of a body was. In scholastic natural philosophy, Descartes finds, the form of a body is a kind of black box that somehow gives rise to its characteristic motions and actions. But as long as the form of a body remains a kind of black box that in itself escapes observation, he thinks, explanations in terms of form are uninformative, and indeed empty.

Boyle on forms

Consider again the following passage from Boyle’s On the origine of formes:
I shall for brevity’s sake retain the word Form, yet I would be understood to mean by it, not a Real Substance distinct from Matter, but only the Matter itself of a Natural Body, considered with its peculiar manner of Existence … For [this] is sufficient to perform the [tasks] that are necessarily required in what Men call a Form, since it makes the Body such as it is, making it appertain to this or that Determinate Species of Bodies, and discriminating it from all other Species of Bodies whatsoever.
According to Boyle in this passage, the form of a body is ‘the matter itself of a natural body, considered with its peculiar manner of existence’. What he means by this, is that the form of a body just is the order and configuration of its material parts. The material parts of a body, with their particular shapes and sizes, make up its form. It is this form that gives a body its physical characteristics.
Note that, although Boyle retains the word form, this does not make him an Aristotelian. The Arisotelians did not believe that the form of a body could be reduced to the order and configuration of its material parts. According to some Aristotelians, the form of a body was best compared to a soul, which made it move and behave in certain ways. Clearly, with his reduction of form to a configuration of material parts, Boyle is very far away from this more traditional notion of form.

Le Grand on forms

Consider again the following passage from Le Grand:
This may also be proved another way. For Substantial Forms were only invented by the [Aristotelians], to make out the Causes of all Actions, that are found in Natural Things, whereof they are the Principles, from whence they do proceed: But these Forms are of no use to the explaining of all these effects; seeing that they themselves own them to be hidden … Wherefore when they say that some Action proceeds from Substantial Forms, they may well be reproached for having recourse to a Principle of Actions, the nature whereof they do not conceive, and by consequence neither can any thing of certainty be gather’d from it: Which alone, in my Judgment, is sufficient to reject them altogether, forasmuch as nothing is to be admitted in Philosophy, which is not clearly and distinctly perceived and known. For what can be more unworthy of a Philosopher, than to make those the Principles of Bodily Things, which he can neither explain by Definition, nor demonstrate by Experience, nor conceive in his Mind?
Would you take him for a Philosopher, who being asked about the Nature of Fire and Water, should tell you that Fire is Fire, and Water, Water? For is it not much the same thing, to say that Fire and Water are such by their Substantial Forms? Or would you think him to be an Interpreter of Nature, who being demanded about the Phases, or Appearances of the Moon or Venus, and the Principles of the Stars, would answer, that they proceed from Forms, as from their Inward Principles? What is this but to call all things by one name, and comprehend them under one and the same Notion?

Le Grand here basically repeats the criticism of Descartes. Indeed, Le Grand was a follower of Descartes living in England, and the main goal of his Entire Body of Philosophy was to make Descartes’s philosophy accessible to an English audience.

His criticism is basically that nobody has ever seen a form, or knows precisely what a form is. To say that the physical properties of a body spring from its form, then, is not at all informative. It is to say that the physical properties of a body spring from something unknown.

Le Grand’s own view is that all bodies can be described as machines, whose physical properties follow from the mechanical interaction between, and motion of, their material parts.

© University of Groningen
This article is from the free online

The Scientific Revolution: Understanding the Roots of Modern Science

Created by
FutureLearn - Learning For Life

Reach your personal and professional goals

Unlock access to hundreds of expert online courses and degrees from top universities and educators to gain accredited qualifications and professional CV-building certificates.

Join over 18 million learners to launch, switch or build upon your career, all at your own pace, across a wide range of topic areas.

Start Learning now