Deductive vs non-deductive arguments
Not every argument is offered with the same intention. Sometimes arguments are offered to prove that something is definitely the case; other times they are offered to show that something is likely or very likely to be true, while leaving it possible that the conclusion may, improbably, turn out to be false.
Before you can tell whether the premises of an argument provide appropriate support for the conclusion, you need to decide which standards to use in your evaluation, and this depends on whether you have an argument of the first or the second kind. The topic for this segment is the distinction between the two, and we will express it as a difference between deductive and non-deductive arguments.
Remember that arguments are groups of statements some of which, the premises, are offered in support of others, the conclusions. There are two kinds of support that premises can give for a conclusion: deductive and non-deductive. When the premises of an argument support the conclusion deductively, we say that the conclusion follows deductively from the premises. Deductive support is the strongest kind of support that premises can give to a conclusion. When the premises of an argument support the conclusion to some significant degree, but do not support it deductively, we say that they support it non-deductively. In this case, the argument is non-deductive.
If you want, you can think of successful deductive arguments as providing conclusive support for their conclusions, assuming the truth of their premises, whereas successful non-deductive arguments give probable, but not conclusive, support for their conclusions.
Let’s start with deductive arguments.
- Definition: A deductive argument is an argument for which the premises are offered to provide logically conclusive support for its conclusion.
If a deductive argument succeeds in providing conclusive support for its conclusion, it would be absurd for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. The kind of support intended in deductive arguments is infallible, inevitable, necessary, “bomb-proof”…
There are phrases people may use in arguments to indicate that they are deductive.
Deductive argument indicators |
---|
it necessarily follows that … |
it logically follows that … |
it absolutely, necessarily, or certainly follows that … |
Here are some examples of deductive arguments:
Every witch is a widow. So it necessarily follows that every witch is female.
It’s good to read the Bible on as many days of your life as possible. Therefore, any day is a good day to start reading the Bible every day.
The number of chicks in the pen is less than 10. The number of chicks in the pen is more than 6. It’s not 7 and it is not 9. The number of chicks in the pen is an integer, because you can’t really have half a chick in the pen. Certainly, then, the number of chicks in the pen is 8.
- Definition: A non-deductive argument is an argument for which the premises are offered to provide probable – but not conclusive – support for its conclusions.
Non-deductive argument indicators |
---|
it is likely that … |
it is probable that … |
it is plausible that … |
It’s cloudy today, so there’s a high probability that it will rain today.
The greediest person who was left alone in the room is Aunt Mary. Chances are that Aunt Mary is the one who stole the apple tart.
Every observed witch is a widow, so it’s likely that every witch is a widow.
Only all the observed wizards that we’ve seen so far were widowers. So the next one we expect to be a widower.
(begin{array}{ll} text{P1} & text{It’s cloudy today. } &text{Therefore, probably,} text{C} & text{It will rain today} end{array})
Now, this whole discussion raises a further question: how are we to decide whether arguments are deductive are non-deductive?
This is a difficult question. Part of the difficulty is that the answer varies with context. Mathematicians only accept deductive arguments, because they are after certain knowledge. Mathematicians are not going to accept arguments that are merely strong. They want deductive arguments. But in a court of law, we cannot only expect deductive arguments. It would be much too demanding and we would almost never be able to put criminals in jail. Instead, cases have to be established beyond reasonable doubt, so that we are very confident in our conclusions, even though we are aware that we might be wrong. We need to strike the right balance, as we don’t want it to be too easy to put people in jail either.
Part of the answer also lies in the principle of charity. The idea is quite simple. Most people are not aware of the distinction between deductive and non-deductive arguments, and they may try and prove things (deductively) when a non-deductive argument would be much more suitable. In that case, the principle of charity tells you to treat the argument as being non-deductive.
Reach your personal and professional goals
Unlock access to hundreds of expert online courses and degrees from top universities and educators to gain accredited qualifications and professional CV-building certificates.
Join over 18 million learners to launch, switch or build upon your career, all at your own pace, across a wide range of topic areas.
Register to receive updates
-
Create an account to receive our newsletter, course recommendations and promotions.
Register for free