Good and bad arguments
We now have all the ingredients to be able to tell when arguments are good or bad. And it’s now quite simple: good arguments are either cogent or sound, otherwise, they are bad. Easy.
Here’s the diagram we introduced in the previous video to help you while judging arguments:
Let’s see how we can use the diagram with some concrete examples. There are two kinds of arguments: deductive and non-deductive.
Now, suppose you’re facing a deductive argument. If the argument is invalid, then it’s a bad argument: it’s an argument that is intended to give conclusive support for it’s conclusion, but fails to do so. Game over.
Think of a student sitting in a mathematics exam and making a crucial mistake in a proof. Then the student’s answer is invalid and therefore, bad. Of course, a professor might have reasons to think that the student’s answer still deserves marks (maybe even full marks) even though the student’s answer is bad – in our understanding of ‘bad’.
If the argument is valid, there are two cases:
Firstly, the argument has false premises, in which case it is not sound. Game over, the argument is bad.
For example:
If there is a purple elephant in the hall, then I am a giant turkey. There is a purple elephant in the hall, therefore, I’m a giant turkey
Liliane is Patrick’s sister, and Patrick is Sylvie’s brother. Therefore, Liliane is Sylvie’s sister.
I have a very strong feeling that my lottery ticket is the winning ticket, so I’m quite confident I will win a lot of money tonight.
If you smoke pot, even only once in your life, you are very likely to start using heroin. You do smoke pot, and therefore, you will probably start using heroin.
About 97% of climate experts agree that humans are causing global warming. Therefore, probably, humans are causing global warming.
Example 1
If you are a confident driver and have never been in an accident, then driving over the speed limit is not dangerous for you or others. You are a confident driver and have never been in an accident. Doubtless, then, driving over the speed limit is not dangerous for you or others.
What’s the conclusion?
- Driving over the speed limit is not dangerous for you or others.
Is the argument deductive or non-deductive?
Is the argument valid?
Is the argument sound?
Example 2
We left our parrot in the house this morning. The nearest neighbour lives one kilometre away. When we got home from work, the parrot was gone. It’s most probable that our neighbour stole the parrot.
What’s the conclusion?
- Our neighbour stole the parrot.
Is the argument deductive or non-deductive?
Is the argument strong?
Example 3
There’s been a popular revolutionary uprising in Tunisia, which is a North African Arab nation. There’s been a popular revolutionary uprising in Libya, also a North African Arab nation. There’s been a popular revolutionary uprising in Egypt, another North African Arab nation. There’s been a popular revolutionary uprising in Bahrain, yet another North African Arab nation. Finally, there’s been a popular revolutionary uprising in Iran, which is an Arab nation. So there will be a popular revolutionary uprising in at least one other Arab country in the next few years.
What’s the conclusion?
- There will be a popular revolutionary uprising in at least one other Arab country in the next few years.
Is the argument deductive or non-deductive?
There are no clear indicator words in this argument to help us in making a choice. If we take the argument to be a deductive one, it would be quite easy to show that it’s invalid. Furthermore, the premises do not seem to be intended to demonstrate beyond doubt that there will be a popular revolutionary uprising in at least one other Arab country in the next few years, but rather to suggest that this is quite likely to happen.
We will thus treat the argument as a non-deductive one.
Is the argument strong?
If all the premises happen to be true, given the number of Arab countries there are, we’ll say the argument is reasonably strong. You might not agree with me, but here’s some explanation. If all premises are true, then they provide evidence that there’s some political instability that is spreading in that region of the world, and this makes it quite probable that the spread won’t stop.
You may not agree with me, but for the sake of the exercise, accept for now that the argument is (reasonably) strong.
Is the argument cogent?
That is, are all the premises true? And the answer is ‘no’, because:
- Iran is not an Arab nation.
- Bahrain is not a North African Arab nation.
So at least two premises of the argument are false. Hence, the argument is not cogent, and is, therefore, bad.
Does that mean that the conclusion of the argument is false?
All we can conclude is that the reasons provided in this argument do not give grounds to believe the conclusion, but it may be that another argument with better premises and the same conclusion is a good one. And regardless of whether or not there’s a good argument for the conclusion, it may still be that there will be a popular revolutionary uprising in at least one other Arab country in the next few years. All we can conclude is that the reasons given in this argument are not enough to make you believe in the conclusion.
Notice that if you didn’t agree that the argument was strong, then you thought it was weak, and a weak argument is a bad argument, so you would agree that the argument is bad, but we would have different reasons for thinking that the argument is bad.
Reach your personal and professional goals
Unlock access to hundreds of expert online courses and degrees from top universities and educators to gain accredited qualifications and professional CV-building certificates.
Join over 18 million learners to launch, switch or build upon your career, all at your own pace, across a wide range of topic areas.
Register to receive updates
-
Create an account to receive our newsletter, course recommendations and promotions.
Register for free